Monthly Archives: October 2017

Sustainable Discourse

Scholars are adept at forming their beliefs on the basis what other people know. Think of a historian’s views about the rise of “scientific management” in the early twentieth century, for example. She will no doubt have done some research of her own, perhaps in the archives of the Bethlehem Steel Corporation, but she will have a learned a great deal more about the subject by reading books and papers from her fellow historians. Indeed, she won’t have learned just about scientific management from these peers, she will have learned about the entire history of the world, going all the way back to her undergraduate studies. All this knowledge forms a frame around her specialization and a foundation beneath it.

When you think about it, this is a marvelous cultural achievement. We don’t just believe that Frederick Winslow Taylor had a profound influence on the organization and management of the modern corporation; we know this. Some of us know this in great detail and others only know the broad outlines. But these are not just “opinions” we hold. It is knowledge we have acquired. And we’ve been able to acquire this knowledge much more easily than the hardworking historians who have uncovered all the documentation and brought it together in their work. All we had to do was read what they had written. Then we knew.

But is that really all there is to it? Is this not almost a magical theory of literary meaning? All I have to do is pass my eyes over the pages of a book, it seems, and suddenly my mind is in a state of knowing! Well, no. As every student knows, it’s not that easy. You read the words and try to understand them. You struggle and you learn.

A very important part of this struggle comes in the confrontation of our own reading with that of others. After we have read a book or essay we discuss it with our peers–be they fellow professors or fellow students. Sometimes, we discuss it with “authorities” or “superiors”, i.e., experts outside our own field or teachers with a better understanding than us students. In those conversations, we find out how well we understand the book we were reading, how effective our struggle with those pages was.

What I want to emphasize is that we did, in fact, form beliefs while reading. We thought we knew something about scientific management after reading a chapter about it. But then, when we discuss with other people who have also read that chapter, we come to see the matter from a different point of view. Sometimes we recognize that we had misunderstood what the book was saying. Sometimes we realize that, however well researched and argued the book may be, the author seems simply to have gotten the facts wrong. Our reading, that is, may turn out not to “hold up” under the pressure of another reader’s take on it.

This is something to be mindful of as you go about your scholarly work. It’s one thing to make up your mind about something; it is another to speak your mind to others. You want to become good at making a claim, i.e., saying (claiming) that something is true. You then want to observe what happens to that claim in a conversation with qualified peers–people who make similar claims about similar things for similar reasons. Does the claim survive the criticism of your peers? Is the claim sustainable in discourse?

The Presumption of Criticism

Scholars often make claims based on research done by other scholars. It is standard practice to rely on the work of others to support or frame your own work. This practice is justified by a set of presumptions that it is our obligation, as scholars, to make true. Doing so does not guarantee that everything you read in a peer-reviewed article is true, but it does justify the (measured) confidence with which we draw on such claims when conducting our research.

In  a word, we presume that the claims made in the literature are subject to ongoing critical scrutiny by qualified peers. Suppose you read in a journal article from 2014 that “between 16% and 40% of expatriate managers return prematurely from their assignment” abroad. What impact should that fact have on your own research? Well, you could be happy to see that the subject you are interested in is, it seems, part of a big problem in the real word. Your ethnographic work on cross-cultural business appears much more relevant in that light. In your own introduction, then, you make this claim, duly citing the source that you found the figure in. You submit the paper for publication, your reviewers recommend publication, and the paper is published. Your claims, including the 16-40% expatriate failure is now opened to the aforementioned “critical scrutiny” of your peers. What happens next?

Well, the reason that you provided a source is that people want to be able to check your facts. Not all readers will do this, but some might. Suppose someone does. And suppose they find the claim embedded in a sentence like the following: “Previous research, reported on by Black and Mendenhall (1989), reveals that between 16% and 40% of expatriate managers return prematurely from their assignment.” Please understand how shocking that is. Your paper made it look like the rate was reported in 2014. We find here that this rate is almost thirty years old! But it gets worse than that. Checking Mendenhall 1989 they will see that the figure is asserted, not on the basis of empirical evidence, but still other studies, going back as far 1971. Looking at those studies, finally, does not solve the mystery either. It’s simply not possible to track down anyone who provides evidence of the 16-40% range.  This is what’s not supposed to happen in scholarship. You should not have cited the rate you did because you, too, should have tried to trace it to its source and failed. You should then have written to the authors of the 2014 paper and pointed out their mistake. The journal should have issued a correction.

It’s only when we believe that such an error-correcting mechanism exists that we can trust the literature on a particular subject. Seeing something we think we can use in an a journal article from four or five years ago, we go to the library and try to see if there’s been any published criticism of it. If not, we check the underlying sources (or evaluate the methods) of the paper in question. We decide that we trust this result and that our readers would trust it too. Then we include it in our own paper. Simply citing the first appearance of a convenient fact is not good enough.

I use the example of expatriate failure rates advisedly. Over twenty years ago, Anne-Wil Harzing discovered that her peers had not been as critical as they should have been when citing high reported rates of expatriate failure. As she put it in a follow up paper in 2002, the paper she wrote as a PhD student about this problem was “was borne out of sheer amazement and indignation that serious academics seemed to get away with something students at all levels were warned not to do.” (Indeed, my example wasn’t pulled out of thin air either, though I have left out the names to protect the guilty. Click here for a more detailed critique.)

We can’t make too much of the courage it takes to challenge your entire discipline in this way as a PhD student. Indeed, I’m not sure it’s even advisable, though Harzing’s hard work, also on other topics, has clearly paid off for her in the long run. What she did was “presumptuous” in a good way. She assumed that standards of scholarly rigor applied in her field even if many scholars seemed to be entirely innocent of them. She acted as though good research was a norm. That’s how we should all work.

Indeed, that’s how most people presume academia works. Mistakes are made but they don’t remain for long. They are caught by critically minded peers and eventually corrected. You can play your part. I highly recommend reading Harzing’s 2002 paper, which is organized around the rules you should be following and examples of how they are broken. Learn them the easy way now. The hard way is not pleasant to think about.

Knowing with Others

What impact should what someone else knows have on your life? That sounds like a pretty big question, but let’s think about this in epistemological terms, as a problem of the theory of knowledge. I want to show that this ultimately tells us something important about specifically academic knowledge and, even more specifically, about academic writing.

First, what does it mean to say that someone knows something? Philosophers often begin with the idea that to know is to have a “justified, true belief” about something. We might want to dispute that, but if we play along for a moment we can consider our original problem as one of deciding what consequences someone else’s true beliefs should have for me. The fact that these beliefs are true tells us that something specific is the case. So, at first pass, we should live our life in accordance with other people’s knowledge on pain of being “unrealistic”. True beliefs, after all, are accurate representations of reality.

Notice that this does not imply that we should believe what other people merely believe. It’s only if they have knowledge that we need to get in line with them.

But a great deal of knowledge doesn’t have immediate practical implications. Astronomers, for example, know that Andromeda will collide with our own Milky Way in a few billion years. Not only is that a long time from now, I’m told it’s not even going to be particularly inconvenient for life in either galaxy when it happens because it will happen very slowly. But astronomers do, in fact, know that this is going to happen. And the consequence for me, I’m happy to admit, is that I believe it. And I think that’s really the first and most important impact that other people’s knowledge should have on our lives. If someone else knows something, then we should believe it.

I mean this “should” in an essentially logical sense. If I say, “Astronomers know that Andromeda will collide with the Milky Way but I don’t believe it,” I am contradicting myself. I can say that astronomers “think” or “claim” or “speculate” or “argue” or, of course, “believe” this, and then declare my own skepticism about it, without contradicting myself. But I can’t claim both that they know it and that I don’t believe it. Why, after all, would I not hold a belief myself if I believe it is true?

But can I say something like, “Astronomers know that Andromeda will collide with the Milky Way but I just don’t understand it”? There’s often something mind-boggling about astronomy and physics and mathematics. We want to grant that astronomers and physicists and mathematicians “know what they’re talking about” but this doesn’t always make things clearer for us, and I’m inclined to take a hard line on this. We should not here say that they know it. We should say that they “say” it and that until we ourselves understand what they’re saying we’re not going to believe it. After all, if I believe something I don’t understand I might not, in fact, be adopting the belief of the people who know it. Maybe we mean two different things by “collide” and in their sense the belief is true but in my sense it is nonsense.

I’ll develop these ideas in subsequent posts this week. But I want to declare my intentions clearly at the outset. I believe that academia should be a place where we are able to believe things that other people know, and where this way of forming beliefs, i.e., on the basis of other people’s knowledge, allows us to claim this knowledge of others as our own. It’s not a place where we believe everything we’re told. It’s a place where people present what they know in a way that opens it for criticism from other knowledgeable people. And the specific ways in which we do this, especially the way we use our writing to foster criticism, means that when we make a claim, and cite our source, we can, at that moment, say we “know” what we’re talking about.

It’s not perfect knowledge. Sometimes we merely believe something that will turn out later to be false. But, within the critical environment of the university, it should be okay to call it knowledge. We are not fools to believe in this way. Or, rather, we expect our peers not to make fools of us. This trust is an important part of what it means to be a scholar, an “academic”. It is sometimes violated, of course; but it is, in fact, the norm.